II. _Nature, and Origin of Conscience_.--While experience seems to point to the existence of something in man witnessing to the right, there is great diversity of view as to the nature of this moral element. The word "Conscience" stands for a concept whose meaning is far from well defined, and the lack of definiteness has left its trace upon ethical theories. While some moralists a.s.sign conscience to the rational or intellectual side of man, and make it wholly a faculty of judgment; others attribute it to feeling or impulse, and make it a sense of pleasure or pain; others again a.s.sociate it more closely with the will, and regard its function to be legislative or imperative.
These differences of opinion reveal the complexity of the nature of conscience. The fact is, that it belongs to all these departments--the intellectual, emotional, and volitional--and ought to be regarded not as a single faculty distinct from the particular decisions, motives, and acts of man, not as an activity foreign to the ego, but as the expression of the whole personality. The question of the origin of conscience, though closely connected with its nature, is for ethics only of secondary importance. It is desirable, however, to indicate the two main theories which have been held regarding its genesis.
While there are several varieties, they may be divided broadly into two--Intuitionalism and Evolutionalism.
1. _Nativism_, of which Intuitionalism is the most common form, regards the conscience as a separate natural endowment, coeval with the creation of man. Every individual, it is maintained, has been endowed by nature with a distinct faculty or organ by which he can immediately and clearly {73} p.r.o.nounce upon the rightness or wrongness of his own actions. In its most p.r.o.nounced form this theory maintains that man has not merely a general consciousness of moral distinctions, but possesses from the very first, apart from all experience and education, a definite and clear knowledge of the particular vices which ought to be avoided and the particular virtues which ought to be practised.
This theory is usually connected with a form of theism which maintains that the conscience is particularly a divine gift, and is, indeed, G.o.d"s special witness or oracle in the heart of man.
Though there would seem to be an element of truth in intuitionalism, since man, to be man at all, must be conceived as made for G.o.d and having that in him which points to the end or ideal of his being, still in its most extreme form it would not be difficult to show that this theory is untenable. It is objectionable, because it involves two a.s.sumptions, of which the one conflicts with experience, and the other with the psychological nature of man.
(1) Experience gives us no warrant for supposing that duty is always the same, and that conscience is therefore exempt from change. History shows rather that moral convictions only gradually emerge, and that the laws and customs of one age are often repudiated by the next. What may seem right to one man is no longer so to his descendant. History records deeds committed in one generation in the name of conscience which in the same name a later generation has condemned with horror.
Moreover, the possibility of a conflict between duties proves that unconditional truth exists at no stage of moral development. There is no law so sacred that it may not in special cases have to yield to the sacredness of a higher law. When duties conflict, our choice cannot be determined by any _a priori_ principle residing in ourselves. It must be governed by that wider conception of the moral life which is to be gained through one"s previous development, and on the basis of a ripe moral experience.[5] (2) Nor is this theory consistent with {74} the known nature of man. We know of no separate and independent organ called conscience. Man must not be divided against himself. Reason and feeling enter into all acts of will, since these are not processes different in kind, but elements of voluntary activity itself and inseparable from it. It is impossible for a man to be determined in his actions or judgments by a mere external formula of duty, a "categorical imperative," as Kant calls it, apart from motives.
Moreover, all endowments may be regarded as divine gifts, and it is a precarious position to claim for one faculty a spiritually divine or supernatural origin which is denied to others. Man is related to G.o.d in his whole nature. The view which regards the law of duty as something foreign to man, stern and unchangeable in its decrees, and in nowise dependent upon the gradual development and growing content of the moral life is not consistent either with history or psychology.
2. _Evolutionalism_, which since the time of Darwin has been applied by Spencer and others to account for the growth of our moral ideas, holds that conscience is the result of a process of development, but does not limit the process to the life of the individual. It extends to the experience of the race. While admitting the existence of conscience as a moral faculty in the rational man of to-day, it holds that it did not exist in his primitive ancestors. Earlier individuals acc.u.mulated a certain amount of experience and moral knowledge, the result of which, as a habit or acquired capacity, was handed down to their successors. From the first man has been a member of society, and is what he is in virtue of his relation to it. All that makes him man, all his powers of body and mind, are inherited. His instincts and desires, which are the springs of action, are themselves the creation of heredity, a.s.sociation and environment. The individual takes its shape at every point from its relation to the social organism of which it is a part. What man really seeks from the earliest is satisfaction.
"No school," says Mr. Spencer, "can avoid taking for the ultimate moral aim a desirable {75} state of feeling."[6] Prolonged experience of pleasure in connection with actions which serve social ends has resulted in certain physiological changes in the brain and nervous system rendering these actions constant. Thus, according to Spencer, is begotten conscience.
While acknowledging the service which the evolutionary theory has done in calling attention to the place and function of experience and social environment in the development of the moral life, and in showing that moral judgment, like every other capacity, must partic.i.p.ate in the gradual unfolding of personality, as a conclusive explanation of conscience it must be p.r.o.nounced insufficient. Press the a.n.a.lysis of sensation as far back as we please, and make an a.n.a.lysis of instincts and feelings as detailed as possible, we never get in man a mere sensation, as we find it in the lower animal; it is always sensation related to, and modified by, a self. In the simplest human instincts there is always a spiritual element which is the basis of the possibility at once of knowledge and morality. "That countless generations," says Green, "should have pa.s.sed during which a transmitted organism was progressively modified by reaction on its surroundings, by struggle for existence or otherwise, till its functions became such that an eternal consciousness could realise or produce itself through them--might add to the wonder with which the consideration of what we do and are must always fill us, but it could not alter the results of that consideration."[7]
No process of evolution, even though it draws upon illimitable ages, can evolve what was not already present in the form of a spiritual potency. The empiric treatment of conscience as the result of social environment and culture leads inevitably back to the a.s.sumption of some rudimentary moral consciousness without which the development of a moral sense would be an impossibility. The history of mankind, moreover, shows that conscience, so far from being merely the reflex of the prevailing customs and inst.i.tutions of a particular age, has frequently {76} closed its special character by reacting upon and protesting against the recognised traditions of society. The individual conscience has often been in advance of its times; and the progress of man has been secured as much by the champions of liberty as by those who conform to accepted customs. In all moral advance there comes a stage when, in the conflict of habit and principle, conscience a.s.serts itself, not only in revealing a higher ideal, but in urging men to seek it.
III. _The Validity and Witness of Conscience_.--It is not, however, with the origin of conscience, but with its capacities and functions in its developed state that Ethics is primarily concerned. The beginning must be interpreted by the end, and the process by the result to which it tends.
1. The Christian doctrine is committed neither to the intuitional nor the evolutionist theory, but rather may be said to reconcile both by retaining that which is true in each. While it holds to the inherent ability on the part of a being made in G.o.d"s image to recognise at the different stages of his growth and development G.o.d"s will as it has been progressively revealed, it avoids the necessity of conceiving man as possessing from the very beginning a full-fledged organ of infallible authority. The conscience partic.i.p.ates in man"s general progress and enlightenment. Nor can the moral development of the individual be held separate from the moral development of the race. As there is a moral solidarity of mankind, so the individual conscience is conditional by the social conscience. The individual does not start in life with a full-grown moral apparatus any more than he starts with a matured physical frame. The most distinctively spiritual attainments of man have their antecedents in less human and more animal capacities.
As there is a continuity of human life, so individuals and peoples inherit the moral a.s.sets of previous generations, and incorporate in their experience all past attainments. Conscience is involved in man"s moral history. It suffers in his sin and alienation from G.o.d, becoming clouded in its insight and feeble in its testimony, but it shares also in his {77} spiritual advancement, growing more sensitive and decisive in its judgments.
(1) Conscience, as the New Testament teaches, can be _perverted_ and debased. It is always open to a free agent to disobey his conscience and reject its authority. On the intuitional theory, which regards the conscience as a separable and independent faculty, it would be difficult to vindicate the terrible consequences of such conduct. It is because the conscience is the man himself as related to the consciousness of the divine will that the effects are so injurious.
Conscience may be (_a_) _Stained_, defiled, and polluted in its very texture (1 Cor. viii. 7); (_b_) _Branded_ or seared (1 Tim. iv. 2), rendered insensible to all feeling for good; (_c_) _Perverted_, in which the very light within becomes darkness. In this last stage the man calls evil good and good evil--the very springs of his nature are poisoned and the avenues of his soul are closed.
"This is death, and the sole death, When man"s loss comes to him from his gain."[8]
(2) But if conscience can be perverted it may also be _improved_. The education is twofold, social and individual. Through society, says Green, personality is actualised. "No individual can make a conscience for himself. He always needs a society to make it for him."[9] There is no such thing as a purely individual conscience. Man can only realise himself, come to his best, in relation to others. The conditions amid which a man is born and reared--the home, the school, the church, the state--are the means by which the conscience is exercised and educated. But the individual is not pa.s.sive. He has also a part to play; and the whole task of man may be regarded as an endeavour to make his conscience effective in life. The New Testament writers refrain from speaking of the conscience as an unerring and perfect organ. Their language implies rather the possibility of its gradual enlightenment; and St. Paul specially dwells upon the necessity of "growing in spiritual {78} knowledge and perception." As life advances moral judgment may be modified and corrected by fuller knowledge, and the perception of a particular form of conduct as good may yield to the experience of something better.
2. "It is one of the most wonderful things," says Professor Wundt, "about moral development, that it unites so many conditions of subordinate value in the accomplishment of higher results,"[10] and the worth of morality is not endangered because the grounds of its realisation in special cases do not always correspond in elevation to the moral ideas. The conscience is not an independent faculty which issues its mandates irrespective of experience. Its judgments are always conditioned by motives. The moral imperatives of conscience may be grouped under four heads:[11] (1) _External constraints_, including all forms of punishment for immoral actions and the social disadvantages which such actions involve. These can only produce the lowest grade of morality, outward propriety, the mere appearance of virtue which has only a negative value in so far as it avoids what is morally offensive. (2) _Internal constraints_, consisting of influences excited by the example of others, by public opinion and habits formed through education and training. (3) _Self-satisfaction_, originating in the agent"s own consciousness. It may be a sense of pleasure or feeling of self-approbation: or higher still, the idea of duty for its own sake, commonly called "conscientiousness." (4) _The ideal of life_, the highest imperative of conscience. Here the n.o.bility of life, as a whole, the supreme life-purpose, gives meaning and incentive to each and every action. The ideal of life is not, however, something static and completed, given once and for all. It grows with the enlightenment of the individual and the development of humanity. The consciousness of every age comprehends it in certain laws and ends of life. The highest form of the ideal finds its embodiment in what are called n.o.ble characters. These ethical heroes rise, in rare and exceptional circ.u.mstances, above the ordinary level of {79} common morality, gathering up into themselves the entire moral development of the past, and radiating their influence into the remotest distances of the future. They are the embodiments of the conscience of the race, at once the standard and challenge of the moral life of mankind, whose influence awakens the slumbering aspirations of men, and whose creative genius affects the whole history of the world, lifting it to higher levels of thought and endeavour.
The supreme example--unique, however, both in kind and degree, and differing by its uniqueness from every other life which has in some measure approximated to the ideal--is disclosed in Jesus Christ. Thus it is that the moral consciousness of the world generally and of the individual in particular, of which the conscience is the organ and expression, develops from less to more, under the influence of the successive imperatives of conduct, till finally it attains to the vision of the greatness of life as it is revealed in its supreme and all-commanding ideal.[12]
3. Finally, in this connection the question of the _permanence of conscience_ may be referred to. Is the ultimate of life a state in which conscience will pervade every department of a man"s being, dominating all his thoughts and activities? or is the ideal condition one in which conscience shall be outgrown and its operation rendered superfluous? A recent writer on Christian ethics[13] makes the remarkable statement that where there is no sense of sin conscience has no function, and he draws the inference that where there is complete normality and perfect moral health conscience will be in abeyance.
Satan, inasmuch as he lacks all moral instinct, can know nothing of conscience; and, because of His sinlessness, Jesus must also be p.r.o.nounced conscienceless. Hence the paradox attributed to Machiavelli: "He who is without conscience is either a Christ or a devil." But though it is true that the Son of Man had no actual experience of sin, and could not, indeed, feel remorse or contrition, yet in so far as He was man there was in Him {80} the possibility of sin, and in the intimate relation which He bore to the human race He had a most accurate and clear knowledge both of the meaning and consequences of evil. So far from saying that Christ had no conscience, it would be nearer the truth to say that He had a perfect conscience, a personality and fullness of consciousness which was a complete reflection of, and harmony with, the highest conceivable good.
The confusion of thought into which Professor Lemme seems to fall is due, we cannot help thinking, to the too restricted and negative signification he gives to conscience. Conscience is not merely the faculty of reproving and approving one"s own conduct when brought into relation with actual sin. It is involved in every moral judgment. A good conscience is not only the absence of an evil one. It has also a positive sanctioning value. The "ought" of life is constantly present.
It is the whole man ever conscious of, and confronted by, his ideal self. The conscience partic.i.p.ates in man"s gradual progress and enlightenment; so far from the individual growing towards a condition in which self-judgment ceases, he is progressing rather in moral discernment, and becoming more and more responsive to the will of Him whose impress and image he bears upon his soul.
The tendency of modern physiological accounts of conscience has been to undermine its authority and empty life of its responsibility, but no theory of the origin of conscience must be permitted to invalidate its judgments. If conscience has any moral worth it is that it contains the promise and witness of G.o.d. The prime question is, What is the nature of its testimony? According to the teaching of Scripture it bears witness to the existence of a higher than man--to a divine Person with whom he is spiritually akin and to whom he is accountable.
"G.o.d"s most intimate presence in the soul." As the revelation of G.o.d"s will grows clearer man"s ideal becomes loftier. Hence a man"s conscience is the measure of his moral life. It reveals G.o.d, and in the light of G.o.d reveals man to himself. We carry a "forever" within our bosom, {81} "ein Gott in unserer Brust,"[14] as Goethe says, which reminds us that even while denizens of this earth we are citizens of heaven and the sharers of an eternal life. Like another John the Baptist, conscience points to one greater than itself. It emphasises the discord that exists between the various parts of man"s nature, a discord which it condemns but cannot remove. It can judge, but it cannot compel. Hence it places man before Christ, and bids him yield to the sway of a new transforming power. As one has finely said, "He who has implanted in every breast such irrefragible testimony to the right, and such unappeasable yearnings for its complete triumph, now comes in His own perfect way to reveal Himself as the Lord of conscience, the Guide of its perplexities, the Strength of its weakness and the Perfecter of its highest hopes."[15]
[1] Davidson, _The Christian Conscience_.
[2] Cf. Symonds, _Studies of Greek Poets_, first series, p. 191.
[3] _Antigone_, Plumptre"s Trans., 455-9.
[4] Cf. Bunsen, _G.o.d in History_, vol. ii. p. 224; also Campbell, _Religion in Greek Literature_.
[5] Cf. Wundt, _Ethik_, vol. ii. p. 66.
[6] _Data of Ethics_, p. 18.
[7] _Proleg._, section 83.
[8] Browning.
[9] _Proleg._, section 321.
[10] _Ethik_, vol. ii. p. 66.
[11] _Idem_.
[12] Cf. Wundt, _Ethik_, vol. ii. pp. 67-74.
[13] Lemme, _Christliche Ethik_, vol. i.
[14] _Ta.s.so_, act iii. scene 2.
[15] Davidson, _The Christian Conscience_, p. 113.
{82}
CHAPTER VI
"THE MIRACLE OF THE WILL"
Closely connected with the conscience as a moral capacity is the power of self-determination, or as it is popularly called--free-will. If conscience is the manifestation of man as knowing, will is more especially his manifestation as a being who acts. The subject which we now approach presents at once a problem and a task. The nature of freedom has been keenly debated from the earliest times, and the history of the problem of the will is almost the history of philosophy. The practical question which arises is whether the individual has any power by which the gulf between the natural and the spiritual can be transcended. Can man choose and decide for a spiritual world above that in which he is by nature involved? The revelation of the good must, indeed, precede the activity of man. But at the same time the change cannot merely happen to him. He cannot simply be a pa.s.sive recipient.
The new life must be taken up by his own activity, and be made his by his own decision and acceptance. This responsive activity on the part of man is the task which life presents to the will.
Much obviously depends upon the answer we are able to give to this question. If man has no power of choice, no capacity of self-determination, and is nothing more than a part of the natural world, then the ethical life is at once ruled out of court.
The difficulties connected with the problem of moral freedom resolve themselves mainly into three: a scientific, a psychological, and a theological.
{83}
I. On the part of natural science it is claimed that man is subject, like everything else, to physical necessity.
II. From the psychological standpoint it is urged that man"s actions are always determined by the strongest motive.