_II.--Concerning Mind_
I pa.s.s on to those things which must necessarily follow from the essence of the eternal and infinite G.o.d.
Thought is the attribute of G.o.d. Individual thoughts are modes expressing the nature of G.o.d in a certain and determinate manner. The order and connection of these ideas coincides with the order and connection of things, therefore G.o.d"s power of thinking is equal to His power of acting. The circle existing in nature and the idea of an existing circle which is also in G.o.d, are one and the same thing, exhibited through different attributes. G.o.d is truly the cause of things as they are in themselves, in so far as He consists of infinite attributes.
The first thing which forms the actual Being of the human mind is nothing else than the idea of an individual actually existing. The essence of man is formed by certain modes of the Divine attributes, that is to say, modes of thought. The idea is the first thing which forms the Being of the human mind. It must be an idea of an individual thing actually existing. Hence the human mind is part of the infinite intellect of G.o.d.
The knowledge of everything which happens necessarily exists in G.o.d, in so far as He forms the nature of the human mind. Man thinks. Modes of thought, such as love, desire, or affections of the mind under whatever designation, do not exist, unless in the same individual exists an idea of a thing loved, desired, etc. But the idea may exist though no other mode of thinking exists. Therefore the essence of man does not necessarily involve existence.
We perceive that a body is affected in certain ways. No individual things are felt or perceived by us except bodies and modes of thought.
The object of the idea const.i.tuting the human mind is a body, or a certain mode of actually existing extension, and nothing else. For if the body were not the object of the human mind, the ideas of the affections of the body would not be in G.o.d, in so far as He has created our mind, but would be in Him in so far as He has formed the mind of another thing.
But we have ideas of the affections of the body; therefore the object of the idea const.i.tuting the human mind is the body actually existing. It follows that man consists of mind and body, and that the human body exists as we perceive it.
_Mind and Body_
Hence we perceive not only that the human mind is united to the body, but also what is to be understood by the union of mind and body. But no one can adequately comprehend it without previously possessing adequate knowledge of the body. In proportion as one body is better adapted than another to act or suffer, the mind will at the same time be better adapted for perception. And the more independent a body may be of other bodies, the stronger will be the understanding of the mind. Thus we can determine the superiority of one mind over another.
All bodies are either moving or resting. Every body moves sometimes slowly, sometimes quickly. Bodies are distinguished from each other by degrees of motion and quiescence, not with regard to substance. All bodies agree in some aspects. Bodies affect each other in motion and rest. Each individual thing must necessarily be determined as to motion or rest by some other thing.
The human body needs for its preservation many other bodies by which it is, as it were, regenerated. The human mind increases its apt.i.tude in proportion to the number of ways in which the body can be disposed. The idea const.i.tuting a formal being of the human mind is not simple, but is highly complex. An idea of each component part of the body must necessarily exist in G.o.d.
The human mind does not know the human body itself, nor does it know that the human body exists, except through the ideas and affections by which the body is affected. Indeed, the human mind is the very idea or knowledge of the human body. These ideas are in G.o.d. Thought is an attribute of G.o.d, and so the thought of the mind originates of necessity in Him. All the ideas which are in G.o.d always agree with those things of which they are ideas, and therefore they are all true.
Falsity consists in privation of knowledge, involved in confusion and mutilation of ideas. For instance, because they think themselves to be free, and the sole reason for this opinion is that they are conscious of their own actions, and ignorant of the causes determining those actions.
n.o.body knows what the will is and how it moves to-day. Those who pretend otherwise and invent locations of the soul, usually excite derision and disgust.
When we look at the sun and imagine it to be immensely nearer to us than it really is, the error arises from the manner in which the essence of the sun affects the body, not merely from the exercise of the imagination.
_Mutual Influences_
The more things the body possesses in common with other bodies, the more things will the mind be adapted to perceive. The human mind possesses an adequate knowledge of the eternal and infinite essence of G.o.d. But the reason why men have not a knowledge of G.o.d as clear as that which they have of common notions is that they cannot imagine G.o.d as they can imagine bodies, and because they have attached the name of G.o.d to the images of things they are accustomed to see. This they can hardly avoid, because they are constantly affected by external bodies. And, indeed most errors arise from our application to the wrong names of things.
For if some one says that the lines drawn from the centre to the circ.u.mference of a circle are unequal, it is because he understands by a circle something different from what we understand by the mathematicians. I did not reckon a man to be in error whom I recently heard complaining that his court has flown into one of his neighbour"s fowls for I understand what he meant.
In the mind there is no absolutely free will. The mind is determined to this or that volition by a cause, which is determined by another cause, and so on _ad infinitum_. The will and intellect are one and the same.
We are partakers of the divine nature in proportion as we more and more understand G.o.d and conform our actions to his will. Our highest happiness consists in this conformity, by which alone the soul finds repose. Those greatly err from the true estimate of virtue who expect to be rewarded for it, as though virtue and the service of G.o.d were our felicity itself and the highest liberty.
_III.--Concerning Mental Affections_
The actions of the mind arise from adequate ideas alone; but the pa.s.sions depend on those alone which are inadequate. The essence of the mind is composed of adequate and inadequate ideas. Joy is a pa.s.sion by which the mind pa.s.ses to a greater degree of perfection; sorrow is a pa.s.sion by which it pa.s.ses to a lesser degree.
Accidentally anything may be the cause of joy, sorrow, or desire. We love or hate certain things not from any known cause, but merely from sympathy or antipathy. If we hate a thing, we seek to affirm concerning it everything that we think can affect it with sorrow, while we deny everything that we think can affect it with joy. From this we see how easily a man may think too much of himself, and of the object which he loves, and on the other hand, may think too little of what he hates.
When a man thinks too much of himself this imagination is termed pride, and is a species of delirium, because he dreams with his eyes open, that he can do all those things to which he attains in imagination alone, regarding them thus as realities, and rejoicing in them so long as he cannot imagine anything to exclude their existence and limit his power of action.
If we imagine that a person loves, desires, or hates a thing which we love, desire, or hate, we shall on that account love, desire, or hate the thing more intensely. If, on the other hand, we imagine that he is averse to the thing we love, or loves the thing to which we are averse, then we shall suffer vacillation of mind. Hence every one strives to the utmost to induce others to love what he loves and to hate what he hates.
This effort is called ambition, which prompts each person to desire that others should live according to his way of thinking. But if all thus act, then all hinder each other. And if all wish to be praised or loved by all, then all hate one another.
Joy is a man"s pa.s.sage from a less to a greater perfection; sorrow is a man"s pa.s.sage from a greater to a less perfection. I say pa.s.sage, for joy is not perfection itself. If a man were born with the perfection to which he pa.s.ses, he would possess it without the affection of joy--a truth the more vividly apparent from the affection of sorrow which is the contrary of joy.
For, that sorrow consists in the pa.s.sage to a less perfection, but not in the less perfection itself, no one can deny, since in so far as a man partakes of any perfection, he cannot be sad.
Nor can we say that sorrow consists in the pa.s.sage to a less perfection, for privation is nothing. But the affection of sorrow is actual, and so can be nothing else than the pa.s.sage to a lesser perfection, that is, the reality by which the power of acting is limited or diminished. As for the definitions of cheerfulness, pleasurable excitement, melancholy, or grief, I omit these, because they are related rather to the body than to the mind, and are merely different species of joy and sorrow.
Love is joy with the accompanying idea of an external cause. Hatred is sorrow with the accompanying idea of an external cause. Devotion is love towards an object which we admire and wonder at. Derision is joy arising from the imagination that something we despise is present in the object we hate. Hope is a joy not constant, arising from the idea of something future or past, about the issue of which we are doubtful. Fear is sorrow not constant, arising in like manner.
Confidence is joy arising from the idea of a past or future object from which the cause for doubting has been removed. Despair is sorrow arising from a like cause. Confidence springs from hope, despair from fear.
Pride is thinking too highly of ourselves from self-love. Despondency is thinking too little of ourselves through sorrow.
_IV.--Concerning Human Bondage and Human Liberty_
Good is that which is useful to us; evil, that which impedes the possession of good. But the terms good and evil are not positive, but are only modes of thought, by which we compare one thing with another.
Thus, music is good to a melancholy mind, bad to a mourning mind, but neither bad nor good to a deaf man. We suffer because we form a part of nature. The power by which we preserve our being is the power of G.o.d, that is part of His essence. But man is subject to pa.s.sions because he follows the order of nature.
An affection can only be overcome by a stronger affection. That which tends to conserve our existence we denominate good. That which hinders this conservation we style evil. Desire springing from the knowledge of good and evil can be restrained by desires originating in the affections by which we are agitated. Thus the effect of external causes on the mind may be far greater than that of the knowledge of good and evil. The desire springing from a knowledge of good and evil may be easily restrained by the desire of present objects. Opinion exercises a more potent influence than reason. Hence the saying of the poet, "I approve the better, but follow the worse." And hence also the preacher says "He that increaseth knowledge increaseth sorrow." We ought to know both the strength and the weakness of our nature, that we may judge what reason can and cannot do in controlling our affections.
Desire springing from joy preponderates over that springing from sorrow.
Man is useful to man because two individuals of the same nature when in sympathy are stronger than one. Nothing could be so good for men as that all should so agree in everything as to form as it were a single body and mind, all seeking the good of all. Hence, men acting in accord with the dictates of reason desire nothing for themselves but what they desire for all. This renders them just, faithful, and honourable.
The knowledge of G.o.d is the supreme mental good, and to know G.o.d is the supreme mental virtue. For G.o.d is the supreme subject of the understanding, and therefore to know or understand G.o.d is the supreme virtue of the mind. But to us nothing can be either good or evil unless it has something in common with us. An object whose nature is absolutely foreign to our own cannot be either good or evil to us, for this reason, that we only call a thing good or evil when it is the cause of joy or sorrow, this is to say, when it increases or diminishes our power to act.
Nothing can be reckoned good except that which is in harmony with our nature, and nothing can be reckoned evil expect what is contrary to our nature, but men cannot be said to agree in nature when they are subject to pa.s.sion. We only act in harmony with the dictates of reason when we agree in nature with others. Men are most useful to each other who are mutually ruled by the laws of reason. But rarely do men live thus in harmony with reason, and thus it comes to pa.s.s that they are commonly envious of each other.
Yet men are seldom disposed to solitude, but answer generally to the familiar description of man as a social animal, for they know that the advantages preponderate over the advantages of social life. They find by experience that by mutual aid and co-operation they can, on the one hand the more easily secure what they need, and on the other hand the better defend themselves from danger.
A man who seeks after virtue will desire others to do so, and this desire will increase in proportion to this increase of his knowledge of G.o.d. The good that a man seeks by the quest of virtue he will wish others to obtain also. This is in accordance with reason, which is the operation of the mind according to the essence of the mind, that essence of the mind being knowledge, which involves the knowledge of G.o.d. The greater the knowledge of G.o.d involved in the essence of the mind, the greater will be the desire that others may seek after the same virtue which the man seeks for himself.
_Economics_
EDWARD BELLAMY
Looking Backward
Edward Bellamy, American social reformer, who sprang into fame in the last decade of the nineteenth century by his book, "Looking Backward," was born in Ma.s.sachusetts, on March 25, 1850. Trained for the Bar, he became a journalist, and devoted his pen to the propaganda of socialism. After the unprecedented success of his socialist novel, in which he describes a suppositious twentieth century revolution from the standpoint of a hypnotised sleeper awakened in 2000 A.D., his modest home at Chicopee Falls became a recognised centre of the socialist movement in the United States.
"Looking Backward" was published in 1888, and was followed by "Equality," in which he expounded his political doctrines in dialogue form, the story being treated merely as a sequel to the earlier book, and entirely subordinated to the more serious aim. We have here preferred to cla.s.sify "Looking Backward" as a work of philosophy, and not as fiction. Bellamy"s championship of the rights of the disinherited, and his enlightened ideas, conveyed in a by no means unimaginative style, gained him many friends and sympathisers. Bellamy died on May 22, 1898.